THE
RIGHT TO PUNISH IN
THOMAS
HOBBES’S LEVIATHAN
The habitual reading of
the Hobbesian foundation of the State, with more or less nuances, reads as
follows: the constitution of sovereignty originates in a pact "moved"
by reciprocal fear or by fear of those who recognize themselves as sovereign.
Such an agreement
consists in accepting the composition of a power that effects the collectivization
of the golden rule. "To be content with so much freedom in his
relationship with other men, as he would allow others in his dealings with
him." In correlation, by "authorization" is granted to the
person holding the common representation "have the use" of the
"greatest power of human powers" the power of the civil person or
Leviathan. Obviously, while for Hobbes the right is not a "property"
but a "freedom", its transfer does not result in alienation but in
the "renunciation" of its exercise. However, when transferring
individual authority -i.e. the right over acts and words - to the
representative and, therefore, "authorize" . allow him to act the
will and judgments of those he represents - this "comes to possess and
exert so much power and so much force" that all wills, out of terror or
fear of that power, conform to their own.
In this article I want
to point out how much more Hobbes says about the origin of the "essence of
the State" and its unity. Following his argument through a series of
inflections, it is observed that the brief description of the pact formula does
not exhaust by itself the central political problem: the relationship between
obligation and resistance. More concretely, Hobbes realizes two fundamental
precisions: it recognizes the reservations to the pact that are derived from
the rights that can not be transferred "neither by means of words nor by
another sign"; and it points out the difference between
"punishment" and "hostility" that enables one to assume the
politicity of the question for the just.
In this article we study
the definition of the "right to punishment" incorporated into
Hobbesian political theory; I affirm that the definition of
"punishment" makes explicit the conflict that goes through the
composition of the sovereign power and, consequently, the very constitution of
the people. That is, in the tension that the sovereign will finds when
personifying the "authority" of the "authors" and defining
what a crime is, it is expressed, as in no other way, the artificial and
unstable political link that demarcates the border between the town and its
enemies. This finding allows Hobbes to infer that, despite the necessary
absolute character of sovereignty, the political nature of the functions of the
representative entails the challenge of conceiving what is just, considering,
in turn, the power relations within the State and also of the particular time
in which those definitions of the just are formulated.
Now, in defining the
"right to punishment", Hobbes makes a double inflection that I seek
to highlight. On the one hand, it identifies in the active presence of the
"multitude" a constitutive limit of the sovereign will itself. On the
other, it elaborates principles that, although considered "natural",
lack a meta-ethical anchoring. In this way, Hobbes presents a sovereign
"duty" without weakening the central premise of his contractualism,
according to which the sovereign does not agree. But, at the same time, without
subordinating politics to morality.
But we also approach
this analysis from the various edges it presents. In section II, the politicity
of the fair question is derived from the difference between
"punishment" and "hostility". In section III, it is argued
in favor of a reading of Leviathan that contemplates the centrality of the will
that Hobbes locates after the right reason and, in correlation, warns the
permanent reconstitution of the conditions of possibility of the order of the
State.
In the definition of the
right to punishment that appears at the beginning of chapter 28 of Leviatán, it
is made explicit that this "right" is not received by means of a pact
but is "founded" on the "right to everything" of each one.
In this way, Hobbes seems to offer the sovereign the exercise of a right
"as absolutely as that which was given in the condition of mere nature and
war of each against his neighbor." Any normative symmetry between the
sovereign and the subjects is thus apparently resolved after the latter's
renunciation of exercising their own right to everything. In other words, by
authorizing the use of the "greatest power of human powers", what
Noel Malcolm considers a legal conflict between overlapping individual rights
is actually remedied.
However, it is necessary
to emphasize that in the exercise of the right to punishment, the
interdependence of life in society described by Hobbes becomes evident and,
consequently, the need to permanently reconstitute the foundation of the State.
That is, by differentiating the punishment from hostility it becomes clear that
the individual or the sovereign are not, according to Hobbes, the "first"
cause of their actions and, much less, the "sufficient cause" of
those. From which follows the impossibility of relegating the foundation of
sovereignty to a singular and finite event occurred in the past or an
unsolvable alternation between order and anarchy. On the contrary, I point out
that the Hobbes Leviathan figure denotes practices of conferring or taking away
honor that constitute a complex symbolic framework in which power is not
"achieved" or "appropriated", but rather "acts".
The understanding of
power as acting implies that it derives from the accidents of the bodies of the
"agent" and the "patient". The Hobbesian subjects are, to
use an expression of Judith Butler, "effect of an earlier power". The
commitment to order is based on the ability of the power to create a second
nature that stabilizes the avatars of the movement. But Hobbes, like Butler,
warns that the power of the subjects makes them "the continued condition
of possibility to remain a subject". In this way, just as the search for
power after power assures the individual the capacity to act in the future, the
constant recomposition of this symbolic complex guarantees to those who occupy
the "seat of sovereignty" to retain the capacity to
"produce" in the future the same effect: obedience.
In short, in the
definition of punishment it is evident that the sovereign, like the solitary
Hobbesian man, is not alone and that, therefore, he acts only on the condition
of attending to the social process in which he effectively exercises his power.
In order to advance this
argument, I consider that the similarity between the prescriptions that
individual and sovereign find in Leviathan should be noted. To the man in the
state of nature, Hobbes advises him to use prospective lenses to see the abyss
that separates frivolous happiness from individual preservation. The chain of
reasoning that is linked in Leviathan (especially between chapters 11 to 15)
tries to show that when looking to the future it must be recognized that the
satisfaction of humanity's prime aspiration (preserving life) depends on the
quality of the interactions with the other. That is, it depends on
"lifestyles" compatible or conducive to peace. For this Hobbes
proposes to correctly identify the "passionate thoughts" that will
direct and govern the mental discourse if you want to achieve "peace as a
means of conservation for men in multitude".
This same
interdependence does not disappear in the exercise of the coercive power of the
sovereign. Although Hobbes argues that the "right to everything" of
the natural person of the representative receives from the agreement the
authority to exercise his freedom alone, does not fail to mention that in the
States that right is deployed with a view to the preservation of
"all". It can be inferred, then, that Hobbesian political science
distinguishes the personal interest of the representative sovereign and the
political body. It even points out the "duty" to make them coincide
so that they can not distinguish between them. Therefore, while the private
"hostility" of man in the state of nature or of the sovereign does
not require any foundation beyond the individual will, the violence of the
sovereign only becomes "punishment" when it is clothed with a prior
conviction, collective authorization; exemplary intention: and, finally, there
is a perception of equity in its administration to the various strata of the
people.
This specificity of the
"right to punishment" allows one to reject a Leviathan reading
according to which the resolution of the conflict between the rights of the
subjects and the sovereign is based on the celebration of the covenant or
coercion that substantiates the obligation. However, I would also like to
highlight two central aspects of my argument. First, the "requirements"
of legality that determine the presence of "punishment" do not limit
power through the pact.12 On the contrary, the Hobbesian sovereign, by
demanding something "by virtue of his power" and not a positive law,
invalidates without injustice the lawsuits that demand the repair of the
positive right that has been violated. Second, the mentioned legality of the
"right to punishment" - a necessary indicator of the shift from the
individual to the public - does not expel private hostility from the sphere of
law. On the contrary, it survives "captured" by the sovereign as a
condition of possibility of the validity of the agreement that enables the use
of the categories of justice in the world.
CONCLUSION
It was said that the
sovereign is the person who holds the power of the State. He has the right to
act by representing his subjects, in ways that they must consider what he has
done as if they had done it themselves. Now, the sovereign is the one who has
that power so necessary for the preservation of social peace as is the right to
punish. What is the foundation of that right? Hobbes can not affirm, without
more, that the sovereign has the right to punish a subject because he has given
it to him: that right can not be granted. The subject, at the moment of being
punished, can not consider the order to punish him as coming from himself: the
necessary object of all human action is the proper good. And yet, the sovereign
must have the right to punish: without such a right, the creation of the State
would be useless.
The foundation of the
right to punish the sovereign is none other than the same right to everything
he had in the state of nature. In the words of Hobbes himself: "I have
also shown that, before, before the Institution of the Republic, every man had
a right to anything, and to do whatever he deemed necessary for his own
preservation, subjugate, wound or kill any a man for that purpose, and this is
the foundation of that right to punish that is exercised in every republic,
because the subjects did not give such a right to the sovereign, but only by
renouncing his, they strengthened him to use his, such as he considered it
necessary, for the preservation of all of them: so that it was not given, but
left, and he alone, and (excepting the limits imposed by the natural law) as
complete, as in the condition of mere nature, and of each one's war against his
neighbor ". Thus, the right to everything from the state of nature
becomes, in the case of the sovereign, the right to punish. In the state of nature
there is no punishment; there can be retribution of evil for evil, but not
punishment. The right to punish arises with the State: it is a way of the right
to all of the state of nature: the way it acquires in the sovereign of a
political community.
But the sovereign not
only has the right to punish: it also has the duty to do so. And such a duty is
a moral duty. In effect: the sovereign is subject to moral laws. That the
subjects can not question their orders does not imply that they can be
arbitrary: the sovereign is always subject to the laws of nature, even when no
subject can discuss whether he has complied with the requirements of these or
not.
Bye…..
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario